Thursday, February 6, 2014
The talk of Giorgio Agamben in Athens: "From the State of Control to a Praxis of Destituent Power"
This is the transcript of a public
lecture by Italian philosopher Giorgio Agamben delivered to a packed
auditorium in Athens on November 16, 2013 and recently published by Chronos e-magazine.
A
reflection on the destiny of democracy today here in Athens is in some
way disturbing, because it obliges us to think the end of democracy in
the very place where it was born. As a matter of fact, the hypothesis I
would like to suggest is that the prevailing governmental paradigm in
Europe today is not only non-democratic, but that it cannot either be
considered as political. I will try therefore to show that European
society today is no longer a political society; it is something entirely
new, for which we lack a proper terminology and we have therefore to
invent a new strategy.
Let me begin
with a concept which seems, starting from September 2001, to have
replaced any other political notion: security. As you know, the formula
“for security reasons” functions today in any domain, from everyday life
to international conflicts, as a codeword in order to impose measures
that the people have no reason to accept. I will try to show that the
real purpose of the security measures is not, as it is currently
assumed, to prevent dangers, troubles or even catastrophes. I will be
consequently obliged to make a short genealogy of the concept of
“security”.
One
possible way to sketch such a genealogy would be to inscribe its origin
and history in the paradigm of the state of exception. In this
perspective, we could trace it back to the Roman principle Salus publica suprema lex – public safety is the highest law — and connect it with Roman dictatorship, with the canonistic principle that necessity does not acknowledge any law, with the comités de salut publique during
French revolution and finally with article 48 of the Weimar republic,
which was the juridical ground for the Nazi regime. Such a genealogy is
certainly correct, but I do not think that it could really explain the
functioning of the security apparatuses and measures which are familiar
to us.
While the state of exception
was originally conceived as a provisional measure, which was meant to
cope with an immediate danger in order to restore the normal situation,
the security reasons constitute today a permanent technology of
government. When in 2003 I published a book in which I tried to show
precisely how the state of exception was becoming in Western
democracies a normal system of government, I could not imagine that my
diagnosis would prove so accurate. The only clear precedent was the Nazi
regime. When Hitler took power in February 1933, he immediately
proclaimed a decree suspending the articles of the Weimar constitution
concerning personal liberties. The decree was never revoked, so that the
entire Third Reich can be considered as a state of exception which
lasted twelve years.
What is
happening today is still different. A formal state of exception is not
declared and we see instead that vague non-juridical notions –like the
security reasons — are used to install a stable state of creeping and
fictitious emergency without any clearly identifiable danger. An example
of such non-juridical notions which are used as emergency producing
factors is the concept of crisis. Besides the juridical meaning of
judgment in a trial, two semantic traditions converge in the history of
this term which, as is evident for you, comes from the greek verb crino; a medical and a theological one. In the medical tradition, crisis means
the moment in which the doctor has to judge, to decide if the patient
will die or survive. The day or the days in which this decision is taken
are called crisimoi, the decisive days. In theology, crisis is the Last Judgment pronounced by Christ in the end of times.
As
you can see, what is essential in both traditions is the connection
with a certain moment in time. In the present usage of the term, it is
precisely this connection which is abolished. The crisis, the judgement,
is split from its temporal index and coincides now with the
chronological course of time, so that — not only in economics and
politics — but in every aspect of social life, the crisis coincides with
normality and becomes, in this way, just a tool of government.
Consequently, the capability to decide once for all disappears and the
continuous decision-making process decides nothing. To state it in
paradoxical terms, we could say that, having to face a continuous state
of exception, the government tends to take the form of a perpetual coup d’état.
By the way, this paradox would be an accurate description of what
happens here in Greece as well as in Italy, where to govern means to
make a continuous series of small coups d’état.
This
is why I think that, in order to understand the peculiar
governmentality under which we live, the paradigm of the state of
exception is not entirely adequate. I will therefore follow Michel
Foucault’s suggestion and investigate the origin of the concept of
security in the beginning of modern economy, by François Quesnais and
the Physiocrates, whose influence on modern governmentality could not be
overestimated. Starting with Westphalia treaty, the great absolutist
European states begin to introduce in their political discourse the idea
that the sovereign has to take care of its subjects’ security. But
Quesnay is the first to establish security (sureté) as the central notion in the theory of government — and this in a very peculiar way.
One
of the main problems governments had to cope with at the time was the
problem of famines. Before Quesnay, the usual methodology was trying to
prevent famines through the creation of public granaries and forbidding
the exportation of cereals. Both these measures had negative effects on
the production. Quesnay’s idea was to reverse the process: instead of
trying to prevent famines, he decided to let them happen and to be able
to govern them once they occurred, liberalizing both internal and
foreign exchanges. “To govern” retains here its etymological cybernetic
meaning: a good kybernes, a good pilot can’t avoid tempests,
but if a tempest occures he must be able to govern his boat, using the
force of waves and winds for navigation. This is the meaning of the
famous motto laisser faire, laissez passer: it is not only the catchword of economic liberalism; it is a paradigm of government, which conceives of security (sureté,
in Quesnay’s words) not as the prevention of troubles, but rather as
the ability to govern and guide them in the good direction once they
take place.
We should not neglect the
philosophical implications of this reversal. It means an epochal
transformation in the very idea of government, which overturns the
traditional hierarchical relation between causes and effects. Since governing the causes is difficult and expensive, it is safer and more useful to try to govern the effects. I would suggest that this theorem by Quesnay is the axiom of modern governmentality. The ancien regime aimed
to rule the causes; modernity pretends to control the effects. And this
axiom applies to every domain, from economy to ecology, from foreign
and military politics to the internal measures of police. We must
realize that European governments today gave up any attempt to rule the
causes, they only want to govern the effects. And Quesnay’s theorem
makes also understandable a fact which seems otherwise inexplicable: I
mean the paradoxical convergence today of an absolutely liberal paradigm
in the economy with an unprecedented and equally absolute paradigm of
state and police control. If government aims for the effects and not the
causes, it will be obliged to extend and multiply control. Causes
demand to be known, while effects can only be checked and controlled.
One
important sphere in which the axiom is operative is that of biometrical
security apparatuses, which increasingly pervade every aspect of social
life. When biometrical technologies first appeared in 18th century in
France with Alphonse Bertillon and in England with Francis Galton, the
inventor of finger prints, they were obviously not meant to prevent
crimes but only to recognize recidivist delinquents. Only once a second
crime has occurred, you can use the biometrical data to identify the
offender. Biometrical technologies, which had been invented for
recividist criminals, remained for a long time their exclusive
privilege. In 1943, US Congress still refused the Citizen Identification Act, which
was meant to introduce for every citizen an Identity Card with finger
prints. But according to a sort of fatality or unwritten law of
modernity, the technologies which have been invented for animals, for
criminals, strangers or Jews, will finally be extended to all human
beings. Therefore, in the course of 20th century, biometric technologies
have been applied to all citizens, and Bertillon’s identification
photographs and Galton’s fingerprints are currently in use everywhere
for ID cards.
But
the extreme step has been taken only in our days and it is still in the
process of full realization. The development of new digital
technologies, with optical scanners which can easily record not only
finger prints but also the retina or the eye’s iris structure,
biometrical apparatuses tend to move beyond the police stations and
immigration offices and spread into everyday life. In many countries,
the access to student’s restaurants or even to schools is controlled by a
biometric apparatus on which the student just puts his or her hand. The
European industries in this field, which are quickly growing, recommend
that citizens get used to this kind of control from their early youth.
The phenomenon is really disturbing, because the European Commissions
for the development of security (like the ESPR, European Security
Research Program) include among their permanent members the
representatives of the big industries in the field, which are just the
old armaments producers like Thales, Finmeccanica, EADS et BAE System,
that have converted to the security business.
It
is easy to imagine the dangers represented by a power that could have
at its disposal the unlimited biometric and genetic information of all
its citizens. With such a power at hand, the extermination of the Jews,
which was undertaken on the basis of incomparably less efficient
documentation, would have been total and incredibly swift. But I will
not dwell on this important aspect of the security problem. The
reflections I would like to share with you concern rather the
transformation of political identity and of political relationships that
are involved in security technologies. This transformation is so
extreme that we can legitimately ask not only if the society in which we
live is still a democratic one, but also if this society can still be
considered political.
Christian
Meier has shown how in the 5th century a transformation of the
conceptualization of the political took place in Athens, which was
grounded on what he calls a “politicization” (politisierung) of citizenship. While until that moment the fact of belonging to the polis was
defined by a number of conditions and social statuses of different kind
— for instance belonging to nobility or to a certain cultural
community, to be a peasant or merchant, a member of a certain family,
etc. — from now on citizenship became the main criterion of social
identity.
“The result was a
specifically Greek conception of citizenship, in which the fact that men
had to behave as citizens found an institutional form. The belonging
to economic or religious communities was removed to a secondary rank.
The citizens of a democracy considered themselves as members of the polis only in so far as they devoted themselves to a political life. Polis and politeia,
city and citizenship, constituted and defined one another. Citizenship
became in that way a form of life, by means of which the polis constituted itself in a domain clearly distinct from the oikos,
the house. Politics became therefore a free public space as such
opposed to the private space, which was the reign of necessity.”
According to Meier, this specifically Greek process of politicization
was transmitted to Western politics, where citizenship remained the
decisive element.
The hypothesis I
would like to propose to you is that this fundamental political factor
has entered an irrevocable process that we can only define as a process
of increasing de-politicization. What was in the beginning a
way of living, an essentially and irreducibly active condition, has now
become a purely passive juridical status, in which action and inaction,
the private and the public are progressively blurred and become
indistinguishable. This process of the de-politicization of citizenship
is so evident that I will not dwell on it.
I
will rather try to show how the paradigm of security and the security
apparatuses have played a decisive role in this process. The growing
extension to citizens of technologies which were conceived for criminals
inevitably has consequences for the political identity of the citizen.
For the first time in the history of humanity, identity is no longer a
function of the social personality and its recognition by others, but
rather a function of biological data, which cannot bear any relation to
it, like the arabesques of the fingerprints or the disposition of the
genes in the double helix of DNA. The most neutral and private thing
becomes the decisive factor of social identity, which loses therefore
its public character.
If my identity
is now determined by biological facts that in no way depend on my will
and over which I have no control, then the construction of something
like a political and ethical identity becomes problematic. What
relationship can I establish with my fingerprints or my genetic code?
The new identity is an identity without the person, as it were, in which
the space of politics and ethics loses its sense and must be thought
again from the ground up. While the classical Greek citizen was defined
through the opposition between the private and the public, the oikos , which is the place of reproductive life, and the polis,
place of political action, the modern citizen seems rather to move in a
zone of indifference between the private and the public, or, to quote
Hobbes’ terms, the physical and the political body.
The
materialization in space of this zone of indifference is the video
surveillance of the streets and the squares of our cities. Here again an
apparatus that had been conceived for the prisons has been extended to
public places. But it is evident that a video-recorded place is no more
an agora and becomes a hybrid of public and private; a zone of
indifference between the prison and the forum. This transformation of
the political space is certainly a complex phenomenon that involves a
multiplicity of causes, and among them the birth of biopower holds a
special place. The primacy of the biological identity over the political
identity is certainly linked to the politicization of bare life in
modern states.
But one should never
forget that the leveling of social identity on body identity begun with
the attempt to identify the recidivist criminals. We should not be
astonished if today the normal relationship between the state and its
citizens is defined by suspicion, police filing and control. The
unspoken principle which rules our society can be stated like this: every citizen is a potential terrorist. But
what is a state ruled by such a principle? Can we still define it as
democratic state? Can we even consider it as something political? In
what kind of state do we live today?
You will probably know that Michel Foucault, in his book Surveiller et Punir and in his courses at the Collège de France, sketched a typological classification of modern states. He shows how the state of the Ancien Regime, which he calls the territorial or sovereign state and whose motto was faire mourir et laisser vivre, evolves progressively into a population state and into a disciplinary state, whose motto reverses now into faire vivre et laisser mourir, as it will take care of the citizen’s life in order to produce healthy, well-ordered and manageable bodies.
The state in which we live now is no more a disciplinary state. Gilles Deleuze suggested to call it the État de contrôle,
or control state, because what it wants is not to order and to impose
discipline but rather to manage and to control. Deleuze’s definition is
correct, because management and control do not necessarily coincide with
order and discipline. No one has told it so clearly as the Italian
police officer, who, after the Genoa riots in July 2001 declared that
the government did not want for the police to maintain order but for it
to manage disorder.
American political scientists who have tried to analyze the constitutional transformation involved in the Patriot Act and in the other laws which followed September 2001 prefer to speak of a security state. But what does security here mean? It is during the French Revolution that the notion of security – sureté, as they used to say — is linked to the definition of police. The laws of March 16, 1791 and August 11, 1792 introduced thus into French legislation the notion of police de sureté (security
police), which was doomed to have a long history in modernity. If you
read the debates which preceded the vote on these laws you will see that
police and security define one another, but no one among the speakers
(Brissot, Heraut de Séchelle, Gensonné) is able to define police or
security by themselves.
The debates
focused on the situation of the police with respect to justice and
judicial power. Gensonné maintains that they are “two separate and
distinct powers,” yet, while the function of the judicial power is
clear, it is impossible to define the role of the police. An analysis of
the debate shows that the place and function of the police is
undecidable and must remain undecidable, because, if it were really
absorbed in the judicial power, the police could no more exist. This is
the discretionary power which still today defines the actions of police
officer, who, in a concrete situation of danger for the public security
act, so to speak, as a sovereign. But, even when he exerts this
discretionary power, the policeman does not really take a decision, nor
prepares, as is usually stated, the judge’s decision. Every decision
concerns the causes, while the police acts on effects, which are by
definition undecidable.
The name of this undecidable element is no more today, like it was in 17th century, raison d’État,
or state reason. It is rather “security reasons”. The security state is
a police state, but, again, in the juridical theory, the police is a
kind of black hole. All we can say is that when the so called “science
of the police” first appears in the 18th century, the “police” is
brought back to its etymology from the Greek politeia and
opposed as such to “politics”. But it is surprising to see that “police”
coincides now with the true political function, while the term politics
is reserved for foreign policy. Thus Von Justi, in his treatise on Policey-Wissenschaft, calls Politik the relationship of a state with other states, while he calls Polizei the
relationship of a state with itself. It is worthwhile to reflect upon
this definition: “Police is the relationship of a state with itself.”
The
hypothesis I would like to suggest here is that, placing itself under
the sign of security, the modern state has left the domain of politics
to enter a no man’s land, whose geography and whose borders are still
unknown. The security state, whose name seems to refer to an absence of
cares (securus from sine cura) should, on the
contrary, make us worry about the dangers it involves for democracy,
because in it political life has become impossible, while democracy
means precisely the possibility of a political life.
But
I would like to conclude — or better to simply stop my lecture (in
philosophy, like in art, no conclusion is possible, you can only abandon
your work) — with something which, as far as I can see now, is perhaps
the most urgent political problem. If the state we have in front of us
is the security state I described, we have to think anew the traditional
strategies of political conflicts. What shall we do, what strategy
shall we follow?
The security
paradigm implies that each form of dissent, each more or less violent
attempt to overthrow the order, becomes an opportunity to govern these
actions into a profitable direction. This is evident in the dialectics
that tightly bind together terrorism and state in an endless vicious
spiral. Starting with French Revolution, the political tradition of
modernity has conceived of radical changes in the form of a
revolutionary process that acts as the pouvoir constituant, the
“constituent power”, of a new institutional order. I think that we have
to abandon this paradigm and try to think something as a puissance destituante, a purely “destituent power”, that cannot be captured in the spiral of security.
It is a destituent power of this sort that Benjamin has in mind in his essay On the Critique of Violence, when
he tries to define a pure violence which could “break the false
dialectics of lawmaking violence and law-preserving violence,” an
example of which is Sorel’s proletarian general strike. “On the breaking
of this cycle,” he writes at the end of the essay “maintained by mythic
forms of law, on the destitution of law with all the forces on which it
depends, finally therefore on the abolition of state power, a new
historical epoch is founded.” While a constituent power destroys law
only to recreate it in a new form, destituent power — insofar as it
deposes once for all the law — can open a really new historical epoch.
To
think such a purely destituent power is not an easy task. Benjamin
wrote once that nothing is so anarchical as the bourgeois order. In the
same sense, Pasolini in his last movie has one of the four Salò masters
saying to their slaves: “true anarchy is the anarchy of power.” It is
precisely because power constitutes itself through the inclusion and the
capture of anarchy and anomy that it is so difficult to have an
immediate access to these dimensions; it is so hard to think today of
something as a true anarchy or a true anomy. I think that a praxis which
would succeed in exposing clearly the anarchy and the anomy captured in
the governmental security technologies could act as a purely destituent
power. A really new political dimension becomes possible only when we
grasp and depose the anarchy and the anomy of power. But this is not
only a theoretical task: it means first of all the rediscovery of a
form-of-life, the access to a new figure of that political life whose
memory the security state tries at any price to cancel.
Giorgio Agamben is
a leading continental philosopher best known for his work on the
concepts of the state of exception, form-of-life and homo sacer.
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment